54 pages • 1 hour read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Culture and Anarchy opens with a lengthy Preface that offers an overview of many of the important ideas that will dominate the work as a whole. Matthew Arnold describes the first aim of his Preface as “to address a word of exhortation to the Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge” (76), lamenting the fact that they have neglected to print more recent editions of Bishop Thomas Wilson’s Maxims of Piety and Christianity (see: Key Figures), a work Arnold cites as an important inspiration for his own thought. Arnold argues that it is essential that the Society should publish classic religious works like Wilson’s to combat “the cartloads of rubbish circulated at present under this designation [of religious texts]” (78). Arnold praises the wisdom of Wilson in both the Maxims and in another work, Sacra Privata, crediting Wilson for his “honesty and good sense united with ardour and unction” (81). Arnold urges the Society to republish Wilson’s works, claiming they will exercise a good religious influence upon Englishmen.
Arnold then passes onto the more specific designs of Culture and Anarchy as a whole. He describes the main idea of the work, which is to argue that true culture is more essential than ever for society. Arnold offers a definition of culture as “a pursuit of our total perfection by means of getting to know, on all the matters which most concern us, the best which has been thought and said in the world” (82) and to apply that knowledge, in turn, to the critical examination of beliefs and values currently in effect. Arnold then admits that intellectuals and cultural believers are often accused of being useless pedants, but nevertheless one of the greatest determining factors of the “solidity” (83) of an Englishmen’s life is “whether he reads during that day, and, far more still [. . .] what he reads during it” (83).
Arnold claims that English culture is often too resistant toward embracing the pursuit of true culture, as many English subjects and commentators tend to be mistrustful of critically examining their notions and beliefs and can be quite defensive when challenged. He offers some examples, such as his attempted critiques of current school regimes and some of the tensions between Nonconformists and the Anglican religious establishment of the Church of England (see: Contextual Analysis). Arnold argues that much of the resistance toward true culture is based on a misunderstanding: “[I]t is not culture’s work or aim to give victory to some rival fetish, but simply to turn a free and fresh stream of thought upon the whole matter in question” (90). Arnold also adds that true culture works toward perfection on both an individual level as well as a more general, societal one.
Significantly, Arnold professes his firm belief that it is “Establishments” (95), and not Nonconformist sects of any kind, that have tended to produce “great works” (95) in both the humanities and the sciences. Arnold criticizes the “provincialism of the English Puritans and Nonconformists” (97), contrasting them unfavorably with the importance of “Establishment” European thinkers. Arnold also touches upon a key concept that will be more fully developed in later chapters of Culture and Anarchy: the contrast between “Hebraism,” the Judaic/Semitic influence in modern Christian culture, and “Hellenism,” the influence of classical Greece and Rome. Arnold makes some remarks about the commonalities of English religious provincialism and American Protestantism, believing both to be frequently too literal and narrow in their religious doctrines and practices.
Arnold asserts that America’s provincialism has left it with little influence upon wider Western culture. He also mentions three social categories in England—"Barbarians” (aristocrats), “Philistines” (the middle class), and the “Populace” (the working class)—which will form the topic of one of his later chapters. Crucially, Arnold claims that the “provincialism” of Victorian English society and American society hinder the creation and spread of true culture due to a set of values that are “calculated to produce miners, or engineers, or architects, not sweetness and light” (113). “Sweetness and light” are, for Arnold, the essence of true culture: a harmonious unity between beauty (“sweetness”) and reason or intelligence (“light”). He believes that English Victorian society, ruled by its obsession with manufacturing, trade, and profits, has left no room for “sweetness and light” to thrive. Arnold then once again returns to religious matters, elucidating further his ideas as to why the narrowness of Nonconformism stymies its development and causes dissension. Arnold argues that true culture can help resolve interdenominational religious squabbles through its commitment to harmony and right reason.
Toward the end of his Preface, Arnold touches upon one of his key arguments: “Now, and for us [the English] it is a time to Hellenise, and to practice knowing; for we have Hebraised too much, and have overvalued doing” (142, emphasis added). Arnold believes that English society, with its emphasis on industry, productivity, and even radical political reforms, has neglected the importance of developing reason, open-mindedness, flexibility, and a greater appreciation for beauty and perfection—the English have adhered too closely to the influence of Hebraism and neglected Hellenism to their cultural detriment.
Arnold follows the Preface with a short Introduction, in which he addresses some of the contemporary critics of culture, such as the politician John Bright and the journalist Frederic Harrison. Both Bright and Harrison criticize men like Arnold for being ineffectual, out of step with the times, and, in Harrison’s words, full of “small faultfinding, love of selfish ease, and indecision in action” (146). Arnold notes that he has personally received criticism over his “indifference to direct political action” (147-148). Arnold defends himself by saying that men of culture are not, at least for the time being, suited for political office. He sees his role as that of a thinker and commentator, claiming, “I am, above all, a believer in culture” (149). He concludes his Introduction by announcing his intention to explain the nature of true culture, why it is important, and why it is worthwhile to have faith in it.
The Preface is one of the most important parts of Culture and Anarchy—indeed, it is much longer than a few of the work’s actual chapters. The Preface outlines many of Arnold’s key ideas and can even be used as an encapsulation of the cultural and social theories Culture and Anarchy propagates as a whole. Most important of all, it also provides valuable insight into Arnold’s personal values and assumptions as a cultural critic.
One of the keystones of Arnold’s views is his firm belief in the worth of “Establishments” and hierarchies. While Arnold believes that true culture is a source of invigoration and even perhaps innovation since it “turn[s] a stream of fresh and free thought upon our stock notions and habits” (82), he is a consistently conservative and cautious thinker in his approaches and values. Arnold’s praise of Bishop Wilson in the opening pages of the Preface reveals his reverence for the authority of past thinkers while also signaling from the outset that his sympathies will always lie with the established Church of England instead of with the more radical, Nonconformist sects. Throughout Culture and Anarchy, Arnold will often reference the religious tensions in his day between Anglicanism and Nonconformism as illustrations of the wider tensions between order and anarchy, tradition and radicalism, and true and false notions of culture.
Arnold’s support for establishments is political as well as religious. In the Preface, Arnold touches upon some of the flaws he believes Victorian English society possesses, such as an obsession with materialism and an idea of “freedom” based on unchecked individualism. Arnold’s belief that misguided notions of “freedom” are too dominant in the English national psyche will play a crucial role in later chapters of Culture and Anarchy, as he will frequently posit that this self-centered conception of freedom is anarchic at heart and therefore a danger to the social order. Just as Arnold presents the national Anglican Church of England as a bulwark against the divisions and chaos of Nonconformism, so too will he valorize the “state” throughout Culture and Anarchy as a bulwark against societal disruption.
Arnold’s conception of what true culture entails is also laid out explicitly in the Preface. In calling culture the “pursuit of our total perfection” (82) via knowing “the best which has been thought and said in the world” (82), Arnold reveals that his view of culture is, at heart, idealistic and aspirational. For Arnold, culture is not just a means of depicting life as it is or a means of providing entertainment; it is transformative, creating a “harmonious perfection” (91, emphasis Arnold’s) and “developing all sides of our humanity” (91). The transformative nature of culture and Arnold’s belief that culture’s essential mission lies in helping humans attain “perfection,” give Arnold’s views of culture a moral and occasionally spiritual dimension as well. True culture is meant to make an individual good, not just knowledgeable or intelligent.
Arnold conceives of culture as a communal enterprise instead of a merely individualistic one: Culture leads to a “general perfection, developing all parts of our society” (91-92, emphasis Arnold’s) instead of transforming individuals in isolation. One of the reasons Arnold will mistrust the English conception of “freedom” so much is partly due to the way it promotes individualism instead of a sense of community, thereby making true culture harder to cultivate. The division between “Hebraism” and “Hellenism” will also prove important later in the work, especially in Chapter 4. Arnold’s view of “Hebraism,” which he associates with literal-mindedness and a narrow worldview, will also influence how he depicts English society, as he believes English culture to be especially susceptible to the Hebraic influence.
Finally, in defining himself as primarily “a believer in culture” (149) while answering his critics who accuse him of political inaction, Arnold provides a glimpse of an issue he will return to toward the end of Culture and Anarchy: his deep reluctance to get involved in direct political action in any form, and what he believes a “believer in culture” should and should not do. While Arnold strongly believes in the transformative power of culture, he believes that the inward nature of that transformation can function apart from direct political action and that believers’ culture should forswear involvement in public life.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
By Matthew Arnold
Books About Art
View Collection
Class
View Collection
Class
View Collection
Essays & Speeches
View Collection
Order & Chaos
View Collection
Philosophy, Logic, & Ethics
View Collection
Politics & Government
View Collection
The Best of "Best Book" Lists
View Collection
Victorian Literature
View Collection
Victorian Literature / Period
View Collection